Future, Present, & Past:
Speculative~~ Giving itself latitude and leisure to take any premise or inquiry to its furthest associative conclusion.
Critical~~ Ready to apply, to itself and its object, the canons of reason, evidence, style, and ethics, up to their limits.
Traditional~~ At home and at large in the ecosystem of practice and memory that radically nourishes the whole person.
Monday, March 8, 2010
Poetry and the Impossible
It's been a quiet couple of weeks here on S.C.T., as I have been trying to collect my thoughts into presentable form in order to respond in my own way to dy0genes' point about poetry. Eventually, as is my wont, I accumulated a sprawling document--far longer and more ill-organized than what I'm posting here. This is the first of what I expect will be two or three parts laying out some of how I see the question of poetry in relation to philosophy.
The Platonic critique of poetry often seems old-fashioned today—who worries about the bad effects of reading poetry anymore?—so it can be a surprise to find it being maintained, quite seriously, by one of the most significant poet/critics of the 20th century. This is Laura (Riding) Jackson, a writer of such uncompromising integrity, such gentle severity, if I can put it that way, that it is hardly surprising that she has not attained the reputation she deserves. Well, I suppose her having dropped poetry altogether might have had something to do with it too. The Collected Poems of Laura Riding, as she was known when she wrote poetry, is a 498-page volume, first published in 1938, three years before she renounced poetry entirely, though she lived until 1991. Her reasons for this renunciation are complex, but they can be summed up, perhaps misleadingly, in one of her titles: “Poet—a lying word.” This phrase, which stood at the head of a poem and of a book of poems, came eventually to sum up her attitude to what had been her vocation. Poetry, she came to believe, “failed.” It enticed one to believe in the possibility of an apt speaking, an articulation of inner human reality, but it failed to deliver this discourse. Poetry, she said, disappoints “the hopes it excites as seemingly the way of perfect human utterance, or articulate truth.” All during her poetic career she had struggled to bring about a language of Platonic purity, a speaking that would be uncontaminated by accident and chance:
Come, words, away from mouths,
Away from tongues in mouths
And reckless hearts in tongues
And mouths in cautious heads—
Come, words, away to where
The meaning is not thickened
With the voice’s fretting substance… (“Come, Words, Away”)
Eventually this impossible and self-refuting urge led her clean out of poetry.
I can’t give an account of Laura (Riding) Jackson, as she called herself after her marriage, that can remotely do justice to her accomplishment, let alone her ambition. And it must be said that if, by her own standards, she did not succeed in the task she set herself as a poet—because, as she came to believe, that task was unrealizable—neither does she accomplish the task she set herself later, of laying out a complete theory of “rational meaning,” by which every word in the language would have one and only one meaning, an account which would finally dispel the encrustations of ambiguity and chance resemblances which make misunderstanding so rife and misleading so easy. To her, language would ideally have been an more elaborate Esperanto, a nomenclature of sense, purged of connotation. One need not appeal to Wittgenstein, Piaget, Saussure, Chomsky, Pinker, Whorff, Vygotsky, or any of the score or more of other major 20th-century theorists of language or language acquisition, to point out how implausible such an ideal is; one can easily open a dictionary and look up, say, “Book: 1. n. A written work or composition that has been published (printed on pages bound together). 2. v. To schedule use of a facility or location ahead of time.”
Riding believed that the poem engaged in a struggle to attain a purity of meaning, to say precisely in a manner that was resisted by its material, language. This struggle is spiritual. “Poetry,” she says in Rational Meaning, the book upon which she labored, with her husband Schuyler Jackson and then alone, until her death, “may be described as an institution devoted to the pursuit of spiritual realism, in relation to religion as an institution devoted to the pursuit of spiritual idealism.” And so we find ourselves with Plato and his objections to the poets’ tales of the gods; or with Heidegger and his exegesis of Hölderlin’s anticipation of the gods’ return.
This is extraordinarily unlikely company for Laura Riding. I can think of few figures she would have wanted less to do with than Heidegger, whose gnomic meditations she would have dismissed with curt impatience. The gulf between Heidegger and Riding, at any stage in her long career, is immense, and I don’t mean to imply any close kinship. But I do say that Heidegger and Riding are each witnesses for the case that the poet’s work is bound up closely with the question of the gods. And as I have cited more than once, Quid sit deus? is called by Leo Strauss the question of philosophy.
“To a poet the mere making of a poem can seem to solve the problem of truth,” Riding later wrote. “But only a problem of art is solved in poetry.” This is indeed the rub. How was it that a problem of art could seem like the problem of truth, so that solving the one seemed to offer, for a tantalizing moment, the solution to the other?
One possible answer is that, given its latitude to treat of nonexistent objects (and even objects that are impossible in the real world), poetry can easily elide the differences between the merely nonexistent and the impossible. That is, poetry speak as if the teacup, the fountain of youth, and the circular square were all just stops along its path, though as objects one is ordinary object, one nonexistent merely, and one both nonexistent and impossible. So, too, when Riding writes of poetry trying to attain a “spiritual realism,” to articulate matters of the spirit in a language scoured of the last traces of ambiguity, she is imagining a nonexistent object. There is no such language.
When she wrote poetry, Riding imagined that it was a way of attaining something beyond language as ordinarily spoken by human mouths; and this “something beyond” is a nonexistent object, an impossible object, not to mention objet petit a (if you like the Lacanian game—and I have no objections if you don’t). When she gave up poetry, she continued to aspire to such a language—she merely changed her avenue of aspiration. Riding provides the most clear case I know of someone self-consciously “running up against the limits of language,” to use the Wittgenstinian phrase once again. Wittgenstein at this stage of his career is usually read as an ally of Russell against the British Idealists and indeed against Meinong, but if sometimes I am nevertheless tempted to adapt the logical apparatus of the Tractatus with a logic of possible worlds, it is precisely with poetry in mind.
I might add that Badiou’s account of poetry with recourse to set theory is a gorgeous attempt—I am not sure how successful—to segue meta-mathematical rigor and poetic allusiveness. In any case, his assertion that poetry, like the other conditions of truth, starts from the undecidable void of the situation (apologies for these technical terms from Badiou’s philosophy, but this post is already too long for me to stuff in more explication) is very like Riding's own description of the poem as a "vacuum."
Frank Ramsey famously remarked of Wittgenstein’s conclusion (“Whereof one cannot speak one must remain silent”) that if we can’t speak about what we can’t speak about, “we can’t whistle it either.” Riding was trying to whistle it. (PMS Hacker thinks that so was Wittgenstein, and I agree… I just think it wasn’t such a silly idea).
I wish I could convey in a brief post the bracing and fierce doggedness with which Riding pursues her objective whether before or after her engagement with poetry, or the music of her genius whether in verse or prose. From the very beginning she refused assessment by any standard but those which were native to her own spirit; it is as if she feared (very rightly, as it turns out) she would be reduced to a function of someone else's scheme. The very first poem that brought her to notice by Allen Tate and John Crowe Ransom demands:
Measure me for burial
That my low stone may neatly say
In a precise, Euclidean way
How I am three-dimensional.
And it ends:
Measure me by myself
And not by time or love or space
Or beauty. Give me this last grace:
that I may be on my low stone
A gage unto myself alone.
I would not have these old faiths fall
To prove that I was nothing at all.
Her ambivalent stance towards feminism, or the "minefield" (as John Ashbery writes) with which she surrounds her poems to safeguard authorial intention, betoken her lifelong resistance to being made a creature of others' stories. (This especially comes out in her biography, for she jealously guarded her own version of events and denounced and demonized anyone who remembered things differently. One cannot say she comes across as wholly sane).
This makes assessing her a difficult matter, and even in presenting her work it is difficult to convey why I find it so compelling. Though she is engaged in an attempt that cannot succeed, she seems less like a child crying for the moon than a brilliant and dogged mariner determined to find the Northwest Passage.
I'll close here with a passage from her late book The Telling, a beautiful work, by turns hermetic, cranky, fastidious, and lyrical, which well sums up both her critique of previous attempts to say beyond what can be said, and her sense of what was at stake. This should lay some ground for next posts.
We hover round the fact of the religions--in which Truth was told in two halves, God, and Man, which did not make One, but half, and again, half. ...Were they to make one story of their separate stories...that story would have in it the flaw of divided purpose that was in all the stories: not wholly for Truth's sake were these stories told. (The Telling, 57.)
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
What a wonderful piece on poetry! Thank you for this. Someone once spoke to me of Rider but I never followed the suggestion up. Now I will. What do you recommend? - From her early and late periods I mean?
ReplyDeleteIn an earlier post you had engaged me and I wanted to answer you. I just wasn't sure how. This post of yours provides another opportunity. Of course, you will have guessed from our correspondence that my unimportant and uninteresting silence does not stem merely from a suspicion about Words and Truth; besides that there is the problem of the Self. Without the self-control of the genuine philosophers one does not even know why one has said what one has just said!
So, Truth is a problem, and the self that we non-philosophers can only barely control is another problem. A third problem is the City. (You of course know I mean Civilization.) One must speak in a manner that doesn't do further damage to the possibility of civilizational survival. Why am I so adamant about this? Without civilization there is no philosophy, - not ever. You know how greatly that troubles me...
Even though I am an advocate (as I believe you are) of the new post-platonic world that will rise after the fall of both modernity and the axial age religions, I am still very uncomfortable with the notion of creating... (God, for a [self-professed] 'Nietzschean', this really is like confessing a murder!) But 'Becoming-Creating' will be the foundation of the World to come! (Just as 'Being-Knowing' was the foundation of these Platonisms now passing away...)
How is it possible that a Nietzschean can be uncomfortable with Creativity? When Nietzsche finally became interesting to me was when I understood that he was speaking of History, and not merely speaking 'truth to power'. Nietzsche as critic, philosophy as criticism, is pointless. Plato and Nietzsche did not do pointless things. It is here that Marx and Nietzsche are as one. The Modern World must change; and it must change for philosophical reasons!
Reasons, not causes; we are not merely billiard balls responding to various forces. Reasons, not whims; we are not merely doing this as an exercise in human creativity! Philosophy is neither physics nor literary theory. Yes, but it incorporates aspects of both. As a reader of medieval philosophy you will know that it was the 'Greek necessitarianism' (as Gilson once referred to it) of the Islamic Falasifa and Latin Aristotelians that made them an abomination to the theologians around them. Against Philosophy, Occasionalism was the weapon of choice in Islam, while Nominalism was what (nearly) destroyed Aristotelianism in the Christian Latin World.
Why rehash this here and now? Because this 'necessitarianism' is of the very essence of philosophy. When one reads the history of philosophy in the manner that Spinoza read the Bible (admitting what the 'authorities' agree on, excluding the rest) one is left with two points: the struggle towards an ever-larger Universalism and the war against nihilism.
Yet again, my comment was too long to be accepted in one note.
ReplyDelete[First, a digression might be in order here to make my point clear about superstitious texts. Now, Spinoza gives us his method of reading for superstitious texts only. Wait a second! Am I maintaining that the texts of genuine philosophers (like scriptures) are superstitious!?! No, of course not. A text is 'superstitious' if it is written by a superstitious person or if it is written by a cautious person in superstitious times. In both cases the text will be 'superstitious'. Now, the $64 question is: 'are there any non-superstitious times?' It was once thought that modernity was, or could be, a non-superstitios time. But post-modernity has quite nicely put an end to all that... Digression ended.]
So? Well, 'ever-larger Universalisms' lead to a world in which destinies can be compared (as Merleau-Ponty once said). That is, we will be able understand the reasons (not merely causes or whims) for human interactions where otherwise we would only see a list of differences. So, how exactly is that Nietzschean? Zarathustra was written for everyone (but philosophers). That people see in it 'spirituality', sex revolution, a call to 'great politics', or the road to authenticity is no accident. "Books are mirrors", Nietzsche said. - And 'Also Sprach Zarathustra' is your proof! It is (according to Nietzsche) from the vantage of philosophical psychology (and only from there) that 'destinies will be compared'. "Psychology is once again the Queen of the Sciences", Nietzsche said. She will reign for at least as long as the new worlds (still to come) based on Becoming-Creating are around.
Ok. But what of Nihilism? Nihilism is the greatest danger of speculation! (Yes, I know. You -and not only you- will think I am slipping into hysteria here...) Post-modernity itself rose because it was seen that no theory (no grand-narrative) could be proven by words. As Nietzsche indicated, the only thing a convincing theory 'proves' is that it is convincing. So what is the answer to nihilism? The body. The body is the abiding clue. (I know, you are wondering if there might be some point to this...) The regularities and repetitions of the body, of nature, are the greatest and most effective argument against nihilism. Nihilism is a problem for thought; not nature. There are no nihilistic animals.
If it turns out to be (as the religious have always threatened) that we are immortal Spirits then it will be in the 'next world' that nihilism will rage in its fullest power. Without the good common sense of the body (God bless it!) we 'spirits' (I mean, of course, the ones that aren't philosophers) would all imagine that we are unique gods and Reality Itself would become (indeed, it would in fact be!) but a succession of whims...
Both Plato and Nietzsche fought (and philosophy itself fights) to prevent that. Now, you perhaps understand my reticence regarding speculation... Anything can be said, anything at all. If we were gods then saying and doing would be exactly the same and reality would be nothing but those innumerable whims... The limitlessness of Speculation is (in non-philosophers) the Déjà vu of an endless nihilism.